Nashville Great Books Discussion Group
A reader's group devoted to the discussion of meaningful books.
Monday, May 30, 2016
In our last reading (Conrad’s Heart of
Darkness, GB1) we learned that “Kurtz was a remarkable man. He had something to say. He said it… He had summed up; he had judged.
‘The horror!’” Kurtz was dying and “the
horror” were the last words Marlow heard him say. It’s up for debate what Kurtz was talking
about. Did the darkness of the world horrify
him? Or was “horror” a term used to
describe the state of Kurtz’s own soul when he knew he was dying? If it’s his own soul, was he sorry for what he
had done? Immanuel Kant would say
no. Even if Kurtz was sorry, it wouldn’t
have done him any good because Kant thinks “repentance which manifests itself
for the first time on the death-bed has no moral worth. Its motive is the nearness of death. If the approach of death were not feared
there would probably be no repentance.”
Marlow
said Kurtz “had summed up; he had judged.”
This falls in line with Kant’s definition of conscience. He says “conscience is an instinct to pass
judgment upon ourselves in accordance with moral laws.” Under Kant’s theory Kurtz had been
overwhelmed in the end by the sheer weight of the judgment of his own
conscience. He had passed judgment upon
himself. Up to that point Kurtz had been
dictator and even demigod of the whole region.
He did whatever he wanted to do and was able to justify killing his
opponents and sticking their heads on poles because these men were rebels and this
is what happens to rebels. It was meant
to serve as a warning to others and enforce obedience from the surrounding
tribes. But was it the right thing to do? Was it “in accordance with moral laws” as
Kant says? Far away from civilization
Kurtz didn’t have to answer that question.
He wasn’t answerable to anyone but himself. Kurtz may have thought it necessary to set himself
up as a terrible tyrant to support his claim as ruler and he may have believed what
he was doing was proof of his strength of character as a leader. But Kant says “the capacity to dismiss the
accusation of a remorseful conscience is not evidence of strength of character,
but rather of wickedness and religious impenitence.”
Kurtz dismissed the instinct of his
conscience and followed another instinct instead, the instinct to power. We learn more about this instinct to power in
Freud (GB1) and Nietzsche (GB5). In his
soul Kurtz was wrestling with two powerful instincts, conscience and
power. This may have been what Marlow
was talking about when he said, “Oh, he struggled! He struggled!
The wastes of his weary brain were haunted by shadowy images; images of
wealth and fame revolving obsequiously round his unextinguishable gift of noble
and lofty expression.” One side of Kurtz
wanted power, wealth and fame while his conscience wanted him to be noble and
lofty. This was his struggle, to choose
between them. There were no police stations
around and no courtrooms to provide external checks on his lust for power. There
was only the inner voice of his own conscience summoning him to stay within the
boundaries of the universal moral law of humanity. Kant says “This law, which is based on reason
and not on sentiment, is incorruptible and incontestably just and pure; it is
the moral law, established as the holy and inviolable law of humanity.” Kurtz left police stations and courtrooms far behind
him when he went deep down the Congo River.
But he couldn’t leave his conscience behind because, as Kant put it, “Conscience
is the representative within us of the divine judgement-seat. It weighs our dispositions and actions in the
scales of a law which is holy and pure.
We cannot deceive it, and, lastly, we cannot escape it because, like the
divine omnipresence it is always with us.”
Kurtz could neither deceive nor escape his conscience. It followed him all the way to his grave. He was a cultivated man but Kant warns that “a
cultivated mind need not be followed by a cultivated conscience.” Kurtz spent a great deal of time and effort
cultivating power. Kant thinks he should
have been cultivating his conscience.
Tuesday, May 24, 2016
Conrad's Heart of Darkness
What makes us the way we are? Is it society
with all of its rules and customs, or is it DNA, something primeval in the
blood? There is a tendency among civilized people to think that philosophy, religion,
or education will provide answers to all
those troubling questions about justice, fate, or good and evil. On the
contrary, Joseph Conrad seems to believe that we, ourselves, are nothing more
than a product of nature, with all those animal instincts still dormant within
our soul. Can education make us better? Perhaps. But the idea that moral progress
is a steady climb upwards from the mud and filth and brutal indifference of
nature is not very reassuring. For every good impulse we have needs to be
ratified daily, and blessed with the knowledge that we are still just one small
step from the darkness composing our primal birth. Wisdom is the recognition
that no society can ever banish completely the origin of our species. We must
live with the knowledge of that inner demon and do what we can to contain it.
Otherwise, like Kurtz, we will surely succumb to that primeval call which ends only
in darkness.
Monday, May 23, 2016
CONRAD 3: Heart of Darkness (Literature and Darkness)
Heart
of Darkness is a story and it’s a good story.
Herodotus tells a good story too in his Persian Wars (GB2) but that’s
history, not literature. Nietzsche also tells
a good story in Thus Spake Zarathustra (GB5) but that’s philosophy, not
literature. Conrad’s main goal is not to
tell us about the past or to analyze ideas.
His goal is to create a work of art that moves the reader on a different
level. How well he succeeds depends entirely
on his ability to create a world in the mind of the reader; how well he can conjure
up images and form meaningful scenes made out of nothing but words. How well did Conrad succeed in doing this in
his story, Heart of Darkness?
In
Chapter 3 the scene has Kurtz on a riverboat heading back down the river, back
to civilization. He’s very sick, in more
ways than one. Marlow says “his
intelligence was perfectly clear; concentrated, it is true, upon himself with
horrible intensity, yet clear… But his soul was mad. Being alone in the wilderness, it had looked
within itself, and, by heavens! I tell you, it had gone mad.” Marlow thought Kurtz was insane. The runaway Russian sailor-adventurer
disagreed. He told Marlow “You can’t
judge Mr. Kurtz as you would an ordinary man.”
Why not? The Declaration of
Independence (IGB2) says “all men are created equal” and should be judged by
the same laws. Why use a different
standard for Kurtz? Conrad doesn’t
say. This isn’t a book about political
philosophy and Conrad isn’t writing a treatise on equality. He’s telling a story that focuses on one
extraordinary man dying on a riverboat in a dark land far from home.
Death
is the ultimate heart of darkness. History
chronicles plenty of deaths. In
Herodotus lots of people die in battle, by drowning, and by disease. Philosophy also has a lot to say on the
subject of death. In Plato’s Apology (GB1)
Socrates thinks death is one of two things: total oblivion or else a place
where good people go to be rewarded and bad people go to be punished. The German philosopher Schopenhauer (GB3)
thinks death is a release from the burden of living. In Rothschild’s Fiddle (GB1) Martha seems to
agree. She’s glad to be leaving her
mean-spirited husband Jacob and her impoverished existence in their miserable Russian
hut. Toward the end of his own life Jacob
reflects on how empty his life had been.
In that way he’s similar to Kurtz.
The result was a song of sadness that touched the hearts of everyone who
heard it. That’s what art can do. Thousands upon thousands of people died in
Herodotus’ history. What were any of
them thinking about in the last few minutes of life? We don’t know. Conrad doesn’t show us what death is like in abstract
terms but how it confronts one individual person on an intensely personal level. For Kurtz it was a dark confrontation. Marlow heard him mumble “I am lying here in
the dark waiting for death.” Marlow didn’t
see oblivion reflected on Kurtz’s face; or reward, or punishment either. Just “an intense and hopeless despair.” The last words Marlow heard him say were “The
horror! The horror!” Kurtz faced death
the same way he faced life. That’s what
impressed Marlow. “He had summed up; he
had judged. The horror! He was a remarkable man.” Kurtz was remarkable because he told the truth. Death is horrible. What was so horrible for Kurtz? Leaving behind all his unfinished plans? Facing darkness alone? The knowledge that his life had been wasted
on greed, lust and power? We don’t know for
sure but we all go down that same dark road eventually. And we travel alone, like Kurtz. Marlow says death “is the most unexciting
contest you can imagine… without spectators, without clamour, without glory.” All of Kurtz’s ambitious plans, all his ivory
and power and glory, all his learning, his “intended” and everything else were of
no help to him in the end. Everyone goes
down that same dark road and everyone ends up in the same dark place; in the grave,
the real heart of darkness. Conrad’s
bleak vision is a remarkably dark literary achievement.
Saturday, May 14, 2016
CONRAD: Heart of Darkness 2 (History and Darkness)
Joseph
Conrad had a dark vision of the human condition. If civilization is the culmination of human
achievement then fire is a good symbol of his vision of civilization. Conrad thinks we’re little better than savage
cavemen sitting around a fire, surrounded on every side by a vast forest of darkness. There’s no other light for hundreds of miles and
darkness threatens to overwhelm us at any moment. The only thing standing between
us and some terrible fate is this one little fire. Most people never have time to think about such
things; nor do we want to. We’re too busy making a living so we just huddle up
closer to the fire. Fire means comfort; cities,
law and order, culture and the pleasures of living among other human beings. But here’s the thought that worried Conrad. What if the fire goes out? Or, even worse, what if we forget how to make
fire?
History
is the way we pass knowledge down from one generation to the next. If civilization is like fire then history is
like a torch. We receive the torch from
others. It’s our job to keep the flame going
and pass it on. Conrad put it this way: “Each
station should be like a beacon on the road towards better things, a centre for
trade of course, but also for humanizing, improving, instructing.” At least that’s the theory. But theory belongs to philosophy, not to
history. When Socrates says “the
unexamined life is not worth living” he’s speaking to everyone at all times in
all places. Philosophy deals with
universal values but history deals with specific people doing specific things
at specific times and places. In this
story a man named Marlow is heading down the Congo River on a steamboat around
the turn of the nineteenth century to bring back a man named Kurtz. It would not have been the same story if it
had happened on the Mississippi River.
And
it wouldn’t have been the same story without the man named Kurtz. In many ways he represents the best that
Western civilization has to offer. “All
Europe contributed to the making of Kurtz” and no doubt he was well-read in
literature, philosophy and history and his painting showed him to be a very good
artist as well. Kurtz was a very
cultured man and “as he was good enough to say himself, his sympathies were in
the right place.” He was on the right
side of history according to the fashionable views of his time. He was a member of the International Society
for the Suppression of Savage Customs and was commissioned to write a report “for
its future guidance.” Marlow read the
report and it had started out all full of optimism. Kurtz wrote that “by the simple exercise of
our will we can exert a power for good practically unbounded.” But something went terribly wrong. He ended his report by scrawling a
handwritten note in the margin: “exterminate the brutes!” What had gone wrong? For months on end no one heard from
Kurtz. There were rumors he was sick and
“had recovered imperfectly.” There were
rumors he was not operating according to the rules of civilized behavior. That’s why Marlow was captain of a steamboat
sent to bring him back, back to civilization and the warmth of domesticated
fire.
Here’s
the special insight that makes Conrad’s story so disturbing. What if the darkness isn’t out there
somewhere, but inside; within us? Kurtz
isn’t the worst among us; he’s among the best.
He went down that river to bring the light of civilization to a dark
land. He went to bring trade and
commerce along with the benefits of civilization; art, literature, history and
philosophy. But Kurtz brought darkness in
with him. Removed from the restraining
influence of civilization he yielded to the primeval temptation of darkness
heard long ago in Genesis (GB1) “ye shall be as gods.” One of the lessons of history is that no
civilization and no individual is exempt from the lessons of history. The fire is fragile and civilization is just a
thin veneer covering up vast darkness. Scratch
that surface and history seems to confirm Conrad’s bleak view of humanity.
Thursday, May 05, 2016
CONRAD: Heart of Darkness 1 (Philosophy and Darkness)
In
our last reading Socrates says “I have no leisure worth mentioning either for
the affairs of the City or for my own estate; I dwell in utter poverty because
of my service to God.” His “service to
God” consisted mostly of talking about philosophy to any Athenian who would
listen. Athens was the place to be if
you wanted to be on the cutting edge of culture and learning. It was the London of the ancient world. Like many folks who live in London today,
Socrates couldn’t imagine living anywhere else.
He flatly refused the option of being exiled to some dull provincial
Geek colony. No thank you very much. Socrates couldn’t see himself pursuing
philosophy in a backwater town somewhere in Thessaly. He wanted to be where the action was and for
a Greek philosopher that meant Athens, the center of the ancient Greek world. Marlow was, in his own way, a philosopher
too; but of a different kind than Socrates.
Socrates wanted to stay put and bloom where he was planted. Marlow had a childhood dream of putting out
to sea and visiting “the dark places of the earth.” So when he became a man that’s exactly what
he did. “He was a seaman, but he was a
wanderer, too, while most seaman lead, if one may so express it, a sedentary
life. Their minds are of the
stay-at-home order, and their home is always with them (the ship) and so is
their country (the sea)… But Marlow was not typical.”
This is Joseph Conrad’s style of philosophy. It doesn’t have the reasonableness of Aristotle or the polished prose of Plato. But it’s philosophy. Aristotle makes sense reading him in a nice comfortable library or in the security of our own homes. And through Plato’s writings we can imagine Socrates talking about truth and justice in front of a crowd of well-educated Athenians. Conrad wants to take philosophy out of that comfort zone. Heart of Darkness has a simple question. What good is philosophy “at the very end of the world… among sand-banks, marshes, forests, and savages?” Conrad doesn’t expect us to answer that it’s no good at all. Instead, he invites the reader to take a journey into darkness, to experience the darkness, to confront it for ourselves. It not a pleasant journey and there’s no initiation into Conrad’s world; no Philosophy 101 course to prepare us beforehand. We have to jump in feet first and, at least for a time, “live in the midst of the incomprehensible.” We have to get a feel for the land and try to make sense of life on a brooding river surrounded by a dark forest. It can be disorienting but it’s only by going into this darkness that we’re really prepared to ask the question. What good is philosophy, here, in this dark place? Well, how does a dark place like ancient London go on to produce a Shakespeare or a John Locke? Aristotle and Plato shine like beacons of light in the darkness. Once upon a time Athens was one of those dark places too. That’s what philosophy is good for.
Marlow
was not a typical sailor and he’s not a typical philosopher either. Sitting on the deck of their ship in London, waiting
for the tide to come in, Marlow remarks to his shipmates, “This also has been
one of the dark places of the earth.” London
has been described in many ways by many people but “one of the dark places of
the earth” isn’t normally what comes to mind.
Marlow is talking about London before it became London; way back when it
was nothing more than a wilderness to the civilized soldiers who manned the
ranks of a Roman army led by Julius Caesar.
Marlow comments that “we live in the flicker… but darkness was here
yesterday… imagine him here at the very end of the world… sand-banks, marshes,
forests, savages; precious little to eat fit for a civilized man, nothing but
Thames water to drink…they must have been dying like flies here… but they were
men enough to face the darkness… all that mysterious life of the wilderness
that stirs in the forest, in the jungles, in the hearts of wild men. There’s no initiation either into such
mysteries. He has to live in the midst
of the incomprehensible.”
This is Joseph Conrad’s style of philosophy. It doesn’t have the reasonableness of Aristotle or the polished prose of Plato. But it’s philosophy. Aristotle makes sense reading him in a nice comfortable library or in the security of our own homes. And through Plato’s writings we can imagine Socrates talking about truth and justice in front of a crowd of well-educated Athenians. Conrad wants to take philosophy out of that comfort zone. Heart of Darkness has a simple question. What good is philosophy “at the very end of the world… among sand-banks, marshes, forests, and savages?” Conrad doesn’t expect us to answer that it’s no good at all. Instead, he invites the reader to take a journey into darkness, to experience the darkness, to confront it for ourselves. It not a pleasant journey and there’s no initiation into Conrad’s world; no Philosophy 101 course to prepare us beforehand. We have to jump in feet first and, at least for a time, “live in the midst of the incomprehensible.” We have to get a feel for the land and try to make sense of life on a brooding river surrounded by a dark forest. It can be disorienting but it’s only by going into this darkness that we’re really prepared to ask the question. What good is philosophy, here, in this dark place? Well, how does a dark place like ancient London go on to produce a Shakespeare or a John Locke? Aristotle and Plato shine like beacons of light in the darkness. Once upon a time Athens was one of those dark places too. That’s what philosophy is good for.
Monday, May 02, 2016
PLATO: The Apology (Politics)
Socrates
was on trial for his life and served as his own lawyer. Depending on the reader’s point of view
Socrates was (a) a terrible lawyer or (b) a brilliant one. The charges against Socrates fall into two
categories: political and religious. The
political charges seem vague to modern readers. “Socrates is guilty of needless curiosity and
meddling interference, inquiring into things beneath Earth and in the Sky,
making the weaker argument the stronger, and teaching others the same.” Socrates went to trial for this? Even though these charges may seem vague to
us, they weren’t vague to the Athenian jurors.
His accusers thought Socrates was guilty of trying to sabotage the whole
Athenian political order. Far from being
a hero, Socrates was, in their view, a dangerous traitor to his country. If Socrates’ goal was to get off then he made
a terrible defense. He mocked his accusers
and left no room for jurors who might have voted for his acquittal under
certain conditions. “Would it not be
possible for you to live in exile, Socrates, if you were silent and kept quiet?” Socrates will make no deals because, as he
publicly proclaims, “to do so would be to disobey God, and therefore I cannot
do it.” He won’t go away and he won’t be
quiet. Socrates informs the jurors that “God
has fastened me to this City. I rouse
you. I persuade you. I upbraid you. I never stop lighting on each of you,
everywhere, all day long.” This is an
inspiring speech but it’s a terrible legal defense if you’re trying to get off in
a capital crime case.
Aristotle believed happiness is “an activity of the soul in conformity with a rational principle.” To achieve happiness we need “a target to aim at to hit the proper mark.” The “proper mark” for Aristotle is the highest good and “this good, one should think, is politics… since all knowledge and every choice is directed toward some good, let us discuss the aim of politics, (i.e. the highest good attainable by action).” This statement helps put Plato’s Apology in perspective. Socrates describes the danger of going into politics when he says “be well assured, Gentlemen of Athens, that had I attempted long since to enter political affairs, I should long since have been destroyed; to the benefit of neither you nor myself. Please do not be angry at me for telling the simple truth. It is impossible for any man to be spared if he legitimately opposes you or any other democratic majority… He who intends to fight for justice, if he is to be spared even for a little while, must live a private rather than a public life… do you think I would have lived so long if I had been in public life and acted in a manner worthy of a good man, fighting injustice?” Plato thought this was the reason why so many good people stay out of politics and Socrates made this prediction: “This is what will convict me, if I am convicted; not Meletus, not Anytus, but the grudging slander of the multitude. It has convicted many another good and decent man; I think it will convict me; nor is there reason to fear that it will end with me.” Socrates was right about that.
Now
here’s the argument why The Apology of Socrates was a brilliant strategy. Socrates may have concluded from the start that
he was doomed. This “trial” was just a
showcase to go through the motions of a proper legal proceeding. Nothing Socrates could do or say would get
him off. So he decides from the
beginning to use his trial as a platform to teach philosophy. Socrates tells a story about the oracle at
Delphi. He could have just gotten right to
the point but first he mentions a man named Chaerephon. Socrates addresses the jurors with these
words. “You surely knew Chaerephon. He was my friend from youth, and a friend of
your democratic majority.” Note how Socrates
says “your” democratic majority. A good
defense lawyer would reject using divisive language in persuading a jury to let
a client go free. But Socrates’ primary
goal isn’t to be set free. He wants to
use this opportunity to teach the Athenians about justice. He wants to expose their ignorance, knowing
full well what the consequences will be.
Aristotle believed happiness is “an activity of the soul in conformity with a rational principle.” To achieve happiness we need “a target to aim at to hit the proper mark.” The “proper mark” for Aristotle is the highest good and “this good, one should think, is politics… since all knowledge and every choice is directed toward some good, let us discuss the aim of politics, (i.e. the highest good attainable by action).” This statement helps put Plato’s Apology in perspective. Socrates describes the danger of going into politics when he says “be well assured, Gentlemen of Athens, that had I attempted long since to enter political affairs, I should long since have been destroyed; to the benefit of neither you nor myself. Please do not be angry at me for telling the simple truth. It is impossible for any man to be spared if he legitimately opposes you or any other democratic majority… He who intends to fight for justice, if he is to be spared even for a little while, must live a private rather than a public life… do you think I would have lived so long if I had been in public life and acted in a manner worthy of a good man, fighting injustice?” Plato thought this was the reason why so many good people stay out of politics and Socrates made this prediction: “This is what will convict me, if I am convicted; not Meletus, not Anytus, but the grudging slander of the multitude. It has convicted many another good and decent man; I think it will convict me; nor is there reason to fear that it will end with me.” Socrates was right about that.